< 607 older entriesHome164 newer entries >

Please, don't put your papers on acedemia.edu

Every now and then, I come across a link to a paper on academia.edu that looks interesting. I myself don't have an account on academia.edu, and I don't want one. This means that in order to look at the paper, I have to go through the following process.

  1. I click "Download (pdf)".
  2. I get confronted with the message: "You must be logged in to download". I can choose to "connect" with Facebook or Google or create an account manually.
  3. I choose the third option, since I don't want academia.edu to access my Google profile (and I don't have a Facebook account).
  4. Now I have to fill in a form asking for "First Name", "Last Name", "Email" and "Password". I enter random expletives in all the fields because I don't want an academia account, I just want to see the bloody paper.
  5. After submitting that form, I get asked whether I have coauthored a paper in a peer-reviewed journal. I choose "No", fearing that otherwise I'll have to answer more questions about those papers.
  6. Next I'm asked to upload my papers. I don't want to upload any papers, so I click "Skip this step".
  7. Next I have to fill in my university affiliation: "University", "URL", "Department", "Position". I enter random expletives.
  8. Next comes a form where I have to enter my "Research Interests". I enter some expletives. (Turns out my expletives are a popular research interest, shared with 32 others.)
  9. Next I'm told again to "connect" with Facebook, even though I already chose not to at the start. I click "I don't have a Facebook account".
  10. Now, finally, I am presented with a link to the paper I wanted to have a look at.

As you can imagine, I rarely go through all that hassle. Usually I look around if I can find the paper somewhere else and give up if I can't.

Centred propositions and objective epistemology

Given some evidence E and some proposition P, we can ask to what extent E supports P, and thus to what extent an agent should believe P if their only relevant evidence is E. The question may not always have a precise answer, but there are both intuitive and theoretical reasons to assume that the question is meaningful – that there is a kind of (imprecise) "evidential probability" conferred by evidence on propositions. That's why it makes sense to say, for example, that one should proportion one's beliefs to one's evidence.

Stalnaker on self-location II

In 2008, I wrote a post on Stalnaker on self-location, in which I attributed a certain position to Stalnaker and raised some objections. But the position isn't actually Stalnaker's. (It might be closer to Chisholm's). So here is another attempt at figuring out Stalnaker's view. (I'm mostly drawing on chapter 3 of Our Knowledge of the internal world (2008), chapter 5 of Context (2014), and a forthcoming paper called "Modeling a perspective on the world" (2015).)

Lewis's argument for Humility

In "Ramseyan Humility", Lewis argues for a thesis he calls "Humility". He never quite says what that thesis is, but its core seems to be the claim that our evidence can never rule out worlds that differ from actuality merely by swapping around fundamental properties. Lewis's argument, on pp.205-207, is perhaps the most puzzling argument he ever gave.

Lewis begins with some terminology.

A note on the scaling of desirability

In The Logic of Decision, Richard Jeffrey pointed out that the desirability (or "news value") of a proposition can be usefully understood as a weighted average of the desirability of different ways in which the proposition can be true, weighted by their respective probability. That is, if A and B are incompatible propositions, then

(1) Des(AvB) = Des(A)P(A/AvB) + Des(B)P(B/AvB).

So desirabilities are affected by probabilities. If you prefer A over B and just found out that conditional on their disjunction, A is more likely then B, then the desirability of the disjunction goes up. That seems right.

Owned possibility and unowned ability

Superficially, modal auxiliaries such as 'must', 'may', 'might', or 'can' seem to be predicate operators. So it is tempting to interpret them as functions from properties to properties: just as 'Alice jumps' attributes to Alice the property of jumping, 'Alice can jump' attributes to her the property of being able to jump, 'Alice may jump' attributes the property of being allowed to jump, and so on.

Perhaps the biggest obstacle to this approach comes from quantified constructions. If 'Alice may jump' attributes to Alice the property of being allowed to jump, then 'one of us may jump' should say that one of us has the property of being allowed to jump. But while this is one possible reading of the sentence, 'one of us may jump' also has a reading on which it states that it is permissible that one of us jumps. There is a kind of de re/de dicto ambiguity here, which suggests that 'may' can not only apply to properties but also to propositions.

Does subjective uncertainty objectively matter?

Let's say that an act A is subjectively better than an alternative B if A is better in light of the agent's information; A is objectively better if it is better in light of all the facts. The distinction is easiest to grasp in a consequentialist setting. Here an act is objectively better if it brings about more good -- if it saves more lives, for example. A morally conscientious agent may not know which of her options would bring about more good. Her subjective ranking of the options might therefore go by the expectation of the good: by the probability-weighted average of the good each act might bring about.

Abstracts on the Philosopher's Index

"The Philosopher's Index" is a commercial software once widely used to search for articles in philosophy journals. These days it is generally easier and faster to search on the open internet. (Even the company behind the Philosopher's Index is not quite sure why the Index is still needed.) However, there is one thing the Index has that can't be found anywhere else: many of its entries contain abstracts of books and articles, apparently provided by the authors themselves. These abstracts are often not part of the published versions, and they can be quite useful to get an authoritative summary, or to see what the author considered to be the main point of a paper.

Microequiprobability

If you spin a wheel of fortune, the outcome -- red or black -- depends on the speed with which you spin. As you increase the speed, the outcome quickly cycles through the two possibilities red and black. As a consequence, any reasonably smooth probability distribution (or frequency distribution) over initial speed determines an approximately equal probability (frequency) for red and black. Here is an example of such a distribution, taken from Strevens.

An allegedly microequiprobable distribution

Notes on Strevens, Bigger than Chaos

I've been asked to review Michael Strevens's new book, Tychomancy. This motivated me to have another look at his earlier book Bigger than Chaos.

The aim of Bigger than Chaos is to explain how apparently chaotic interactions in highly complex systems often give rise to simple large-scale regularities, such as the laws of thermodynamics, the stability of predator/prey population levels, or the economic cycle. The basic explanatory strategy, which Strevens calls enion probability analysis (EPA), consists in aggregating the probabilistic dynamics for the individual components of a complex system into a probabilistic dynamics for macro-level features of the system.

< 607 older entriesHome164 newer entries >