< 475 older entriesHome296 newer entries >

Centering C-propositions

Let's call the class of counterfactual circumstances at which a sentence S is true the C-proposition expressed by S. This is more or less what Kaplan calls the "content" of S. Here are three reasons why the circumstances constituting a C-proposition should be understood as centered possible worlds rather than old-fashioned uncentered worlds.

First reason: centering is needed for modal embeddings. The standard use of C-propositions is the analysis of modal constructions: "it is possible that hummingbirds can fly backwards" is true iff there is at least one relevant circumstance w at which "hummingbirds can fly backwards" is true. Now take a sentence such as "it is early afternoon", or "it is starting to rain". It doesn't make much sense to say of an entire world that it is early afternoon there, or starting to rain. So on the standard view, on which the circumstances in C-propositions are uncentered worlds, we first have to fix a time and place, presumably by drawing on the utterance context: "necessarily, it is early afternoon" is true iff it is early afternoon at every possible world at the time and place of the utterance. So "necessarily, it is early afternoon" is true whenever it is uttered on an early afternoon. That seems wrong.

No longer true

Here's something puzzling. Suppose sometime in 1869, Frege uttered

1) more people today die of tuberculosis than of cancer.

As far as I know, this was true in 1871, but it is no longer true now. Today, more people die of cancer than of tuberculosis. On the other hand, suppose Frege also uttered

2) I am not particularly well-known among philosophers.

This, too, is no longer true. Today, Frege is exceptionally well-known among philosophers.

Truth at a world, truth at a banana

Everyone who has taught Kripke and Putnam to undergraduates knows that philosophers nowadays use "truth at a world" in a special, technical sense that requires a lot of explaining. The most straightforward way to assign a sentence a truth value at another world w is to consider an utterance of the same words in w and ask whether or not that utterance is true. But this is not what we mean. Nor do we ask what truth value the sentence has conditional on the assumption that our world is w. (Lewis uses "truth at a world" in roughly this sense in "How to define theoretical terms"; the current convention appears to be really quite new.) What, then, do we mean? I find most introductions of the concept utterly obscure: I'm told to identify the 'proposition expressed' by a sentence in the actual world, and then to 'evaluate' this entity at another possible world. What on earth does that mean?

Fake zebras

Apparently, there's a Chinese park charging people to have pictures with a Dretske-style fake zebra. The experiment reveals the underappreciated role of fun in epistemology:

"We saw right away that the zebra is fake, but we are here for fun, so it doesn't really matter," said a mother who had just paid for her child's picture.

According to the City Evening News, the park says it doesn't know if the horse is a zebra or not: "It's not that important. It is for fun," said a spokesman.

Same-saying

Somewhat related to the Most Certain Principle is the following constraint on semantic content:

Same-Saying Constraint: if A utters a sentence S1, and B utters a sentence S2, then they say the same thing iff S1 and S2 have the same content.

"Saying the same thing" is here obviously not meant as "saying something with the same content". That would make the constraint empty. Rather, it's supposed to be an intuitive, pre-theoretic notion.

The Most Certain Principle

Cresswell calls this the Most Certain Principle:

MCP: if we have two sentences A and B, and A is true and B is false, then A and B do not mean the same.

Last year, I thought that this principle was most certainly false: if I say something true that is false at another world w, and somebody in w says something with the same content, then our utterances mean the same while they differ in truth value. To quote myself,

The property of being two meters away

I believe that there is such a property as being two meters away. -- Not two meters away from me, or from somebody else, or two meters away from something or other. Just two meters away.

Admittedly, there is a sense in which something can be two meters away only relative to some point of reference. But compare properties like being empty and being bent. There is a sense in which, strictly speaking, persisting things can be empty or bent only relative to a time: this cup here is empty at the present time while it was full 5 minutes ago. Likewise, at least prima facie many things are empty or bent only relative to worlds: the cup is empty at the actual world, but full at other possible worlds. That's why properties are often modeled as something like functions from worlds and times to sets of objects.

Meanwhile...

...in the latest issue of Nature, some physicists published an empirical refutation of

'realism' -- a viewpoint according to which an external reality exists independent of observation.

They also advocate considering

the breakdown of [...] Aristotelian logic, counterfactual definiteness, absence of actions into the past or a world that is not [sic] completely deterministic.

As far as I can tell, what they actually found is evidence against certain local hidden-variable theories that survived Bell's inequalities. Aristotelian syllogisms and realism (in the above sense) seem to be thrown out by the principle that if you throw out the bath water, you might as well throw out the whole bathroom.

Should one act only upon what one knows?

Searching. Mary is in the park, looking for Fred. She recognizes Fred's friend Ted some distance away on the left. Knowing that Fred is often in the park with Ted, she turns that way.
Waiting. Alexandre is waiting for Veronique in a cafe. He's been waiting for several hours now, and is doubtful that Veronique will ever show up. Nevertheless, he thinks it is worth waiting some more.

Mary and Alexandre are acting rationally here, even though Mary does not know that Fred is to the left, and Alexandre does not know that Veronique will ever show up. Even if it turns out that both were wrong, I wouldn't blame them for their decisions.

Pragmatic intrusion, validity, and compositional pragmatics

Sometimes, implicatures appear to survive under embedding. Take

1) the column will fail and the bridge will collapse,

which in a suitable context implicates that (the speaker believes that) the bridge will collapse as a result of the column failing. This implicature is still present if (1) gets embedded in, say, a conditional:

2) if it rains, the column will fail and the bridge will collapse;
3) if the column will fail and the bridge will collapse, you'll be in trouble.

(2) is likely to convey that if it rains, the bridge will collapse as a result of the column failing, and (3) that if the bridge will collapse as a result of the column failing, then you'll be trouble.

< 475 older entriesHome296 newer entries >