Lewis on Quasi-Realism

In "Quasi-Realism is Fictionalism" ((Lewis 2005)), Lewis seems to suggest that Blackburn's quasi-realism about moral discourse is a kind of fictionalism. The suggestion is bizarre. Has Lewis made silly mistake? (Spoiler: No.)

Let's compare what quasi-realism and fictionalism say about moral discourse.

Blackburn's quasi-realism (as presented, e.g., in (Blackburn 1984, ch.6) and (Blackburn 1993)) is a brand of expressivism. According to Blackburn, moral statements like (1) don't serve to describe special facts, but to express moral attitudes.

(1)Eating people is wrong.

The exact nature of moral attitudes won't matter, except that they are not beliefs.

Fictionalism is harder to pin down. Different authors give different definitions; Lewis gives none. But we get a sense of what he has in mind. According to Lewis, a fictionalist is disposed to utter sentences of a certain type even though she doesn't believe that they are true, understanding them as tacitly "prefixed" or "prefaced" by a disclaimer which cancels the commitment to truth. Lewis cites (Joyce 2001) as an example of moral fictionalism. Joyce suggests that we should keep uttering things like (1), but clarify – when pressed in the philosophy seminar – that these utterances are only pretend-assertions, not real assertions: that we only make-believe what we say.

These two views about (1) are obviously different. The quasi-realist does not think that (1) is, strictly speaking, false, but that we may nonetheless utter it with an understanding that we don't really believe what it says. (Blackburn 2005) repeats this point at length, in response to Lewis, but the point should have been thoroughly clear from Blackburn's other writings. How could Lewis have missed it?

So far, we've only looked at the title of Lewis's essay ("Quasi-Realism is Fictionalism"). Blackburn's response barely engages with the content. Does Lewis have an argument for his surprising claim?

If we skim the paper for such an argument, we find on p.319 what seems to be the central argument:

Blackburn's quasi-realism is just this kind of moral fictionalism. […] One of Blackburn's avowed aims is to earn the right to say what the 'moral realist' does: that means either being or make-believedly being a realist. Another of his avowed aims is to avoid the realist's errors: that means not being a realist. Taking these aims together, he aims to make-believedly be a moral realist.

As (Jenkins 2006) points out, this argument seems to rest on the false assumption that realism and fictionalism are the only options: either (1) expresses belief in a mind-independent moral fact, or it expresses make-believing such a fact. Expressivism denies both.

What a silly mistake!

Well, let's stop skimming and have a closer look at what Lewis actually says. I think it's clear that Lewis isn't talking about statements like (1) when he says that the quasi-realist wants to "say what the 'moral realist' does".

Lewis puts 'moral realism' in scare quotes because he uses it in a technical sense. This is explained on p.315f.:

Let us […] reserve the name 'moral realism' for a moral theory that is committed to [a distinctive error]: that there are properties […] such that we can detect them; and such that when we do detect them, that inevitably evokes in us pro- or con-attitudes towards the things that we have detected to have these properties.

So here is what the 'moral realist' says:

(2)There are properties that we can detect and that inevitably evoke pro- or con-attitudes towards the things that we have detected to have these properties.

When Lewis says that Blackburn's avowed aim is to earn the right to say what the 'moral realist' does, I think he obviously meant things like (2), not things like (1), which are not at all distinctive of 'moral realism'.

As the first paragraph of the paper makes clear, Lewis is interested in a well-known puzzle: if the quasi-realist really echoes everything the realist says, if "he even echoes all the realist says about moral psychology and metaethics" (p.314), how is the position different from realism?

This puzzle does not arise for old-fashioned expressivism (as in (Ayer 1936), for example). Old-fashioned expressivism is easy to tell apart from realism by that fact that it declares, for example, (3) and (4) to be false.

(3)It is true that eating people is wrong.
(4)It is a fact that eating people is wrong.

The aim of Blackburn's quasi-realist program is to extend the expressivist semantics so as to vindicate our apparently realist moral discourse, including statements like (3) and (4). Lewis's paper begins with the supposition that this program succeeds: that the expressivist semantics for (1) can be extended to (3) and (4) and beyond, up to the point where the quasi-realist has "earned the right to echo everything the moral realist says" (p.314).

One might wonder whether Blackburn really wants to vindicate statements like (2). In his response to Lewis, Blackburn distinguishes between our practice itself and speculative philosophical theorizing about our practice. (2) looks like a piece of philosophical theory, rather than something that's integral to our ordinary practice. The aim of quasi-realism, he explains (on pp.331f. of (Blackburn 2005)), is not to vindicate erroneous philosophical theories.

But the example Blackburn gives of an erroneous philosophical theory is not like (2). And there is certainly pressure towards vindicating (2). Blackburn explicitly does want to vindicate statements like (5) and (6) and (7) and (8).

(5)Eating people has the property of being wrong.
(6)Whether something is wrong is independent of us and our attitudes.
(7)We can recognize whether an act is wrong.
(8)If someone recognizes that an act is wrong, they inevitably have a con-attitude towards it.

Isn't (2) just a logical consequence of statements like these? Aren't we allowed to draw the inference?

In any case, if 'moral realism' subscribes to (2) and quasi-realism does not then there is no puzzle. We could easily tell apart the two views by what they say about (2). The premise of Lewis's paper is that realism and quasi-realism can't be told apart in such a simple way.

By hypothesis, then, the quasi-realist is prepared to accept and utter (2). But doesn't the quasi-realist also want to deny (2)? To make the point even more obvious, consider (9).

(9)Hume's projectivist account of morality is deeply mistaken.

It is only a short step from (5) and (6) and (2) and uncontroversial facts about Hume, to (9). So 'anti-realism' endorses (9), and quasi-realism – ex hypothesi – follows along. But wouldn't Blackburn want to deny (9)? At the level of belief: doesn't Blackburn believe that Hume's projectivist account is essentially right?

Again, one might respond that quasi-realism was never meant to be that far-reaching: the quasi-realist only wants to echo harmless statements like (3) and (4) and (5), not things like (2) and (9). And again, it will be hard to draw the line, and Lewis simply sets this possibility aside, because it doesn't raise an interesting puzzle. Let's set it aside as well.

Another thing the quasi-realist could do is accept (2) and (9) as true, and leave it at that. Projectivism, she might say, was the ladder on which we've climbed to quasi-realism, but once we have climbed the ladder, we had to kick it away. We have to disavow projectivism, and presumably expressivism, and naturalism.

This looks deeply unappealing. Is there any other way out?

There is: fictionalism!

The quasi-realist might utter (2) and (9), in a suitable context. But she might also clarify, when pressed in the philosophy classroom, that she doesn't genuinely believe (2) and (9).

That's why quasi-realism is fictionalism. The argument goes like this.

  1. 'Moral realism' is committed to statements like (2).
  2. If quasi-realism succeeds, it licenses uttering these statements.
  3. But the quasi-realist doesn't believe things like (2).
  4. So the quasi-realist only make-believes things like (2).

This is not unlike the argument quoted above. And it's not a stupid argument.

The crucial point is that (2), unlike (1), is a suitable object of genuine belief, even by the quasi-realist's lights. Quasi-realism is motivated, to a large extent, by the belief that (2) is false. If the quasi-realist's utterance of (2) were to express genuine belief, she would believe that (2) is both true and false.

(It wouldn't help much to declare, implausibly, that (2) expresses a moral attitude. The quasi-realist who doesn't want to kick away the ladder still wants to reject (2) when explaining and motivating her position.)

Here is Lewis's concluding comment, coming right after the argument:

[Quasi-realism] earns the right to agree with all the moral realist says in just the same way explicit fictionalism does, whether or not it goes on to earn that right twice over by offering its special semantics. (pp.319f.)

Lewis here acknowledges that the quasi-realist may already have a way to agree with the realist by means of their special (expressivist) semantics, and that this way is distinct from the fictionalist way. (Hence 'twice over'.) So Lewis clearly didn't think, as Blackburn and Jenkins and other commentators assume, that the quasi-realist interpretation of moral discourse amounts to a fictionalist interpretation. (Jenkins at least raises this as a puzzle, at the end of her paper.)

How does the quasi-realist's special semantics explain why it's OK to utter (2)? I don't know. To my knowledge, Blackburn has nowhere offered a sufficiently detailed semantics (or semantics+pragmatics) that would cover statements like (2).

In fact, one might suspect that the quasi-realist's special semantics only covers statements which express moral attitudes. Since (2) doesn't express a moral attitude, it would follow that the special semantics doesn't license uttering (2). So it wouldn't license echoing everything the realist says. Quasi-realism would have failed on its own terms, as Lewis understands them.

This means that quasi-realism may require fictionalism not only to remain consistent, but also to fulfil its ambition of echoing realism. The special semantics does that job for moral statements, but perhaps not for statements like (2). Here, fictionalism may be needed to fill the gap.

I think that's why Lewis says "whether or not it goes on to earn that right twice over by offering its special semantics", suggesting that it's an open question whether the special semantics alone is enough.

So. Is the quasi-realist account of first-order moral discourse a fictionalist account of that discourse? Of course not. But if the quasi-realist wants to echo more than the realist's first-order discourse, if she also wants to echo more theoretical statements that may seem to follow from our first-order discourse, then she arguably must endorse a kind of fictionalism.

That was Lewis's point.

Ayer, Alfred Jules. 1936. Language, Truth and Logic. Dover Publications.
Blackburn, Simon. 1984. Spreading the Word. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
———. 1993. Essays in Quasi-Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———. 2005. “Quasi-Realism No Fictionalism.” In Fictionalism in Metaphysics, edited by Mark Eli Kalderon, 322–38. Oxford University Press.
Jenkins, C. S. 2006. “Lewis and Blackburn on Quasi-Realism and Fictionalism.” Analysis 66 (4): 315–19. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/66.4.315.
Joyce, Richard. 2001. The Myth of Morality. Cambridge University Press.
Lewis, David. 2005. “Quasi-Realism Is Fictionalism.” In Fictionalism in Metaphysics, edited by Eli Kalderon, 314–21. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Comments

# on 30 May 2025, 15:46

"Isn't (2) just a logical consequence of statements like these? Aren't we allowed to draw the inference?"

In order for this sentence not to beg the question against Blackburn, it has to be taken in quite a specific form. (2) specifically has to follow from (5)-(8) under the logic and semantics that Blackburn provides for statements like (5)-(8). Certainly, if (5)-(8) are treated like sentences expressing beliefs, treated according to normal basically-classical logic, then (2) seems follow. But Blackburn explicitly doesn't want to treat (5)-(8) in this way; and this has an effect on what inferences we are allowed to draw.

I think – though it's been a long time since I've read Blackburn – that the semantics he gives for ethical statements actually results in a much weaker logic (or 'logic'). And without having any Blackburn books on hand to check, I wonder if that doesn't block the inference from (5)-(8) to (2). Certainly it seems like it *should* block this inference, if the semantics are to do the work Blackburn requires.

If you can't conclude (2) from (5)-(8) _within Blackburn's logic_, then this whole line of argument breaks down. When you ask Blackburn "Aren't we allowed to draw the inference?", he can respond "No, and I've explained why. You can disagree with me on this, but that just means disagreeing with my quasi-realist project; assuming quasi-realism, this inference is blocked, and I'm able to go on being not-a-fictionalist with no tension."

Obviously this answer requires that Blackburn's semantics for ethical statements actually block the inference. But this seems right: Blackburn's ability to distinguish quasi-realism from other positions depends crucially on his ability to give an account of moral inference that is powerful enough to allow us to do moral reasoning, but not so powerful that it allows us to reach metaphysically realist conclusions. If the logic is too weak, he collapses into an old-style expressivist; if it's too strong, he has to be either a realist or an error theorist. Blackburn says as much himself, albeit not in these exact words.

# on 31 May 2025, 08:44

Thanks Peter!

I'm not enough of an expert on Blackburn to tell whether you're right about the inference to (2). My impression is that he doesn't want to invalidate classical logic for reasoning with mixed moral/non-moral statements. He certainly goes to great lengths trying to explain why all instances of Modus Ponens are valid.

But what do you mean by "this whole line of argument breaks down"? In the blog post, I try to defend a new interpretation of Lewis's argument. I don't think you're challenging this interpretation. Nor do you really challenge Lewis's argument, in my reconstruction. The argument begins with the explicit premise that quasi-realism licenses echoing everything the moral realist wants to say. You're right that it's not obvious whether Blackburn would want to subscribe to that premise. (I said as much in the blog post.) But it fits how the term "quasi-realism" is often introduced. For example, this is Joyce in the SEP entry for "Moral Anti-Realism": "The quasi-realist is someone who endorses an anti-realist metaphysical stance but who seeks, through philosophical maneuvering, to earn the right for moral discourse to enjoy all the trappings of realist talk." So I think it's fair to explore how this kind of view (whether or not Blackburn accepts it) would work.

# on 31 May 2025, 09:01

Re: "this whole line of argument", I see now that was ambiguous. I did not mean to refer to the argument of Lewis's paper: your interpretation of the paper is that "the quasi-realist will [quasi-]assert (2) and maybe (9)" is a _premise_ of Lewis' argument. I agree your reconstruction of Lewis's argument is valid. I was referring rather to your own, less-fleshed-out argument as for why this premise is plausible: that we're "allowed to draw the inference" from (5)-(8) (which the quasi-realist unambiguously wants to assert) to (2) and perhaps to (9). That was the line of argument in the two sentences of yours I quoted, and it was this line of argument I meant to refer to. Apologies for the ambiguity.

I think that for (your reconstructed version of) Lewis' argument to be more than merely valid, for it actually to be interesting-or-potentially-sound, then you have to have some reason to think this premise is more than trivially false. I think you see this yourself: you write that "if 'moral realism' subscribes to (2) and quasi-realism does not then there is no puzzle." My point was just that the "pressure" you describe for the quasi-realist to assert (2) might just be based on a misunderstanding of what the quasi-realist theorist is allowed to assert and to refrain from asserting. Indeed, as you yourself note, Blackburn in his response to Lewis tries to wriggle out of Lewis' point by trying to avoid asserting (2). My claim is that whether or not the quasi-realist actually does face pressure to assert (or "assert") (2) comes down to questions about the _quasi-realist's_ theory of the semantics of ethical statements, and not intuitions about which inferences we are "allowed" to draw: the quasi-realist can happily deny those intuitions, and even explain away why we have them, _so long as_ their own theory is able to block the inference.

# on 31 May 2025, 09:53

OK, I think we largely agree on the big picture.

I still think there is considerable pressure for the quasi-realist to accept (2), from two sources. One comes from what quasi-realism is advertised to achieve: to license speaking just like the moral realist. If the position doesn't license saying (2), it doesn't fulfill this promise. The other comes from the intuitive validity of the argument from (5)-(8) to (2). I don't agree that the quasi-realist can happily reject intuitions about validity. The general project is to explain our practice *as it is*. That's why there's so much work on how to explain the validity of modus ponens from a quasi-realist perspective. The idea that they could simply reject Geach's modus ponens inference as invalid doesn't even seem to cross Blackburn's or Gibbard's mind.

I suppose our remaining disagreement is largely verbal or historical: it's about how to understand "quasi-realism".

# on 31 May 2025, 11:16

I agree this is mostly historical, but I still think that's not uninteresting, as it relates to what is supposed to be attractive about quasi-realism.

Regarding advertising, Blackburn (like, I think, Gibbard) is quite clear, and quite consistent (including in his response to Lewis, which you cite), that he wants to license the part of moral realist–speak that counts as part of ordinary ethical practice, but he very much does _not_ want to license that part of moral realist–speak that should rather be understood as theoretical reflections on that practice. I think this distinction is pretty central to the quasi-realist project. Maybe the absolute most simplified slogan form of quasi-realism ('you can speak just like the moral realist') _might_ be interpreted in a different manner than this; but slogans can be cashed out in numerous different ways. (Blackburn can justify such slogan as saying 'you can speak just like the moral realist _in all the ways that matter_'; the moral realist will disagree with him about what 'matters', of course, but he's allowed to advertise his view this way.)

So I think the more substantive point here is that you think the inference from (5)-(8) to (2) is part of 'our moral practice', and failing to license it would be tantamount to failing to license Geach's modus ponens. I think Blackburn here, again, would lean on the distinction between theoretical and practical: Geach's modus ponens is made up entirely of first-order ethical concepts and statements linked by logical connectives, so it is uncontroversially part of our moral practice; whereas (2) is purely theoretical, so Blackburn is happy to do without it.

I take it that your question is basically, does Blackburn have the right to this distinction? Don't we all want to affirm 'mixed' statements like (5)-(8), which are kind of theoretical but also integral to our ethical practice? And once we have such 'mixed' statements, doesn't that break the 'firewall' between theory and practice, allowing us to infer 'purely theoretical' conclusions that Blackburn officially wants to disown like (2)? I think the answer to this question comes down to Blackburn's semantics and logic. As I say, the quasi-realist has to walk a fine line: their logic has to be strong enough that it can allow for e.g. Geach's MP to be valid, but not so strong that it allows '(5)-(8), therefore (2)' to be valid. If Blackburn's semantics do indeed successfully walk this line (and I don't know if they do), then he's earned the right to distinguish between theory and practice: he can cash out the distinction in terms of his logic.

More broadly, I think part of the _point_ of quasi-realism is that it's supposed to license a distinction between statements that are part of our ethical practice, and statements that are part of theorising about that practice, in a way that does not in general allow you to conclude the latter from the former. You can be an anti-realist in theory, but a realist in practice, and not find that contradictory. When you say that Blackburn wants to explain our moral practice as it is, this is correct: but this explanation doesn't necessarily have to _vindicate_ all of it. And indeed, the point of projectivism in his metaethics is to explain but not vindicate why we tend to assert things like (2).

What distinguishes Blackburn from the error theorist is precisely that he wants to vindicate _some_ or even _much_ of our practice – specifically, the parts that really are 'practice' as opposed to 'pure theory'. You might not find the project of firewalling practice from theory attractive (certainly, I don't think Lewis did); and even if you're somewhat sympathetic in principle, you might be sceptical that Blackburn has earned the rights to the distinction; but I do think this is the driving motivation, the _point_ of the quasi-realist project. If we ask 'what happens if we try quasi-realism but without this distinction?', we shouldn't be surprised to find that it collapses into a species of some other view.

Add a comment

Please leave these fields blank (spam trap):

No HTML please.
You can edit this comment until 30 minutes after posting.